Skip to main content

Prediction Markets

Prediction markets are openly traded markets that trade assets which are linked to different potential future outcomes. The purpose of prediction markets is to aggregate information from a diverse set of independent actors. Prediction markets have been shown in numerous studies to have more accurate prediction capabilities than other methods such as polls. The reason for this is that they require the actors trading in the markets (also known as informants) to put stake in the game and allows them to profit if they correctly predict a future outcome - while risking loss if their predictions are incorrect.

The examples presented here are based on the examples in R. Hanson's watershed paper Shall We Vote on Values, But Bet on Beliefs?.1

Categorical Prediction markets

In its simplest form, a prediction market tries to predict the probability of a particular outcome DD of a future event. For example, the future event might be the U.S. presidential election of 2016 (for the sake of this example, imagine that it's early 2016) and DD might be "The Democratic Party wins the 2016 U.S. presidential election".

To aggregate information about the probability of DD, a centralized institution (the bank) sells pairs of the following assets at 1$: "Worth 1$ if DD", "Worth 1$ if not DD". These assets are called outcome asset tokens (sometimes referred to as binary options). Each token represents a possible outcome of the election.

While the market is open, these slips are sold to the actors of the market by the bank. The price of the individual assets will be decided by the market makers who provide liquidity to the market.

Before the market ends, a date for its end is defined. For example, the Iowa Electronic Markets' 2016 U.S. Presidential Election Markets, in which traders could bet on which of the major parties wins a greater share of the popular vote in the 2016 election, opened on November 19, 2014 and closed November 10, 2016.2

When the market closes, the outcome must be reported. For centralized prediction markets, this is usually done by the bank, and the report is based on trusted news media.3 On decentralized prediction markets, the report is issued by an entity called oracle, which must be incentivized to provide correct information (or discouraged from providing incorrect information).

Once the outcome is reported (for the presidential election: DD is false), the winning outcome (in this case "Worth 1$ if not DD") can be traded in for 1$ at the bank, while the losing outcome ("Worth 1$ if DD") is rendered worthless. It's winner-take-all! We say that the market resolves to "Worth 1$ if not DD".

important

After market close, the price of each token is irrelevant to the trader. Only the correct outcome asset token has any remaining value.

For example, suppose Alice bought 10 shares of "Worth 1$ if not DD" at 0.6$ and Bob bought 5 shares of "Worth 1$ if DD" at 0.4$. Then November 10, 2016 comes along and the Republican Party is declared the winner of the election. Thus, Bob's shares are rendered worthless, while Alice may trade her 10 shares in for 10$, leaving her a fat profit of 4$ (minus trading fees, see below).

But how did the market reveal information about the future event? The price at which actors are willing to buy "Worth 1$ if DD" measures the actors' confidence that DD will occur. In fact, the price of one share of "Worth 1$ if DD" in USD is considered to be equal to the market's prediction of the probability that the event DD occurs. If, for example, actors are willing to buy shares of "Worth 1$ if DD" at 0.7$, then the markets predicts the probability of D to be about 70%, and the probability of "not DD" to be about 30%.4

The longer a market is active, the more refined the prediction is expected to be. The prediction at market close should reflect all information available to the traders over the course of the market. If a market remains open while the events on whose outcome bets are made unfold, then the value of the outcome to which the market will eventually resolve will likely approach 1$, and all other outcomes will become nearly worthless. For example, during the IEM's 2016 U.S. Presidential Election Markets, the average price of DEM16_WTA, the token for "$1 if the Democratic Party nominee receives the majority of popular votes cast for the two major parties in the 2016 U.S. Presidential election, $0 otherwise", at market close was 0.973$ (see also 2016 US Presidential Election Winner Takes All Market).

Depending on the market maker strategy and the correctness of the aggregated information, the bank might suffer a loss. In practice, the market makers will take trading fees from the actors to mitigate these risks.5

Markets with More than Two Outcomes

In general, a prediction market can involve any (finite) number of assets. For example, during the Kusama Derby, three prediction markets opened on the Zeitgeist Battery Park chain: Who will win the first/second/third parachain slot on Kusama? The tokens of these markets:

  • Karura
  • Moonriver
  • Khala
  • Robonomics
  • Kilt
  • Equilibrium
  • Hydra
  • Shiden
  • Darwinia
  • None

The None token is a catch-all option representing the following outcomes:

  • None of the other teams listed win the slot
  • The parachain auction does not complete in time before the market's end date of June 30, 2021
  • More than one team split the slot with different lease periods
  • Any other unforeseen outcome

The collection of outcome tokens should be mutually exclusive (no two outcomes may both occur) and exhaustive (there must be a token for every possible outcome). A good rule of thumb when designing a prediction market that does not ask a yes-no question is to define a catch-all token (like None from the Kusama Derby), which wins if the outcome matches no other token. In fact, as the bidding on the last parachain slot only ended July 6, 2021, and the Kusama Derby ended on June 30, 2021, the reported outcome of the third market of the Kusama Derby was None, even though Khala did eventually win the third parachain slot auction.

During the Zeitgeist Closed Beta, a market for a football game between the Minnesota Vikings and the Dallas Cowboys had the following tokens:

  • Cowboys win by 6 or less points
  • Cowboys win by 7 or more points
  • Vikings win by 6 or less points
  • Vikings win by 7 or more points
  • Tied
  • Cancelled due to bad weather or other unforeseen events

Scalar Prediction Markets

The type of market described above is a discrete prediction market in which outcomes form clear categories. For betting on the value of some quantity or measurement, scalar prediction markets are used. For example, "What's the Tesla stock price on Monday at market close?" Unlike discrete prediction markets, these are not winner-take-all.

For scalar markets, the outcome assets are known as "Long" and "Short", though the outcome that the market will eventually resolve to will be a number. In scalar markets, instead of the categories (e.g. Yes/No, Under/Over, etc.), the continuous outcome range is set at market creation, defined by an upper and lower numerical bound. The outcome range specified by these bounds does not necessarily cover all possible outcomes.

If the market resolves to a number within the outcome range, both Long and Short outcome assets will be redeemable at between 0$ and 1$, proportional to where the resolved outcome lies along the range (and totalling 1$). If the market resolves to a number that lies below or above the range, then one of the Long and Short outcome assets would be redeemable to 1$ (and the other would have no value).

For example, suppose that the upper and lower bounds for Tesla's stock price are 1,000$ and 1,200$. If traders buy Long at 0.60$, then they bet that Tesla will as least be at

1, ⁣000$+0.6200$=1, ⁣120$1,\! 000\$ + 0.6 \cdot 200\$ = 1,\! 120\$

at market close. If you want to bet that Tesla will be at 1,050$ at market close, then you buy Long at 0.25$ or lower (you predict that Long will redeem for at least 0.25$) and Short at 0.75$ or lower (you predict that Short will redeem for at least 0.75$).

If the market then resolves to 1,180$, then Long may be redeemed for 0.90$ and Short for 0.10$. If the market resolves to a value above 1,200$, then Long is worth 1.00$ and Short is worthless.

Another example of a scalar prediction market is the Pres16_VS Market on the Iowa Electronic Markets. Instead of betting on the who wins the larger amount of votes in the popular vote, traders are betting the major parties' share in the popular vote. This means that the lower bound is 0 and the upper bound is 1, and buying a share of UDEM16_VS (Long) at 0.55$ means that you predict that the Democratic Party will have at least a 55% share of the popular vote (cast between the two parties), and buying UREP16_VS (Short) at 0.40$ means that you predict that the Republican Party will have at least a 40% share of the vote (cast between the two parties). At market close on November 10, 2016, the average prices were 0.519$ for UDEM16_VS and 0.484$ for UREP16_VS (see 2016 US Presidential Election Vote Share Market). Note that the actual shares of the Democratic and Republican Party of the popular vote (cast between the two parties) are approximately 51.11% and 48.89% (see 2016 United States presidential election).

Historical Background

Prediction markets can be traced back to writings of Ludwig von Mises and Frederik Hayek, however it is the economist Robin Hansen that is perhaps the best-known proponent of them today. Hansen's writings have a very significant theoretic implication on how to implement prediction markets in a blockchain setting. He posits in Shall We Vote on Values, But Bet on Beliefs?1 that the primary problem that can be solved is that of info problems, that is the difficulty of aggregating information among many individuals with all different views of the subject.

In relation to the info problems described above, Hanson (in the same paper) points out that speculative markets show striking success in their ability to aggregate information. He says "That is, active speculative markets do very well at inducing people to acquire info, share it via trades, and collect that info into consensus prices that persuade wider audiences."


  1. Shall We Vote on Values, But Bet on Beliefs?, The Journal of Political Philosophy, 21(2), pp. 151–178 (2013).

  2. Note that this closing date is after the end of the election.

  3. For example, this is the strategy for the 2016 U.S. Presidential Election Markets (see here):

    The election data posted on the New York Times official website at 5pm CST on Wednesday, November 9, 2016, or as soon after as available, will be the official source used to determine payoffs. In the event that the two parties' popular votes are not reported at that website by midnight, Wednesday, November 9, 2016, the Washington Post official website will become the official source. Should neither source report popular vote by midnight Wednesday, the information reported in the print version of the New York Times on Thursday, November 10, 2016, or as soon thereafter as reported, will be used. In the event that the election is delayed or postponed, liquidation will take place in a timely fashion after the close of polling sites for the popular vote.

    The judgment of the IEM Governors and Directors will be final in resolving questions of interpretation and typographical or clerical errors."

  4. The reasoning here is that if the probability of outcome DD is xx, then the expected profit of buying the outcome token for the price of yy is xyx - y. Thus, ignoring trading fees, a trader who believes that the probability of DD is xx should expect to make a profit by buying at a price lower than xx and selling at a price higher than xx. So the price should, in the long run, approach xx.

  5. If a bank suffers a loss from providing liquidity to a market, this loss may be viewed as the cost of receiving the information aggregated by the actors.